Different uses for voting
need different types of voting. |
Compare One-Winner
|
Compare single-winner voting systems:
Condorcet efficiency Utility efficiency Nearness to the center Condorcet EfficiencyEven though Condorcet winners can beat each of the other candidates in one-on-one elections, most voting rules do not always elect them. Given 100 elections with no voting cycles, what percentage of the 100 Condorcet winners will each voting system elect? This number is a voting system’s "Condorcet efficiency". To estimate the efficiency of each voting system, several political scientists have used computers to simulate groups of voters.[Samuel Merrill III coined this term and defined it: “The Condorcet efficiency of a voting procedure is the proportion or percentage of a class of elections (for which a Condorcet candidate exists) in which the voting system chooses the Condorcet candidate as winner.” (Merrill: Glossary)] Table 1. Condorcet Efficienciesin computer simulated elections with 4 candidates and 4 issues data from Chamberlin, Cohen, and Coombs, 1984 21 Voters
1000 Voters
|
Table 2. Condorcet Efficiencies
in computer simulated elections with 5 candidates and 1000 voters
from Merrill, 1988, page 24.
Voting Rule | Random Society | D= 2 | D= 4 | D= 2 | Spatial models | D= 2 | D= 4 | D= 2 | D= 4 |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Dispersion = 0.5 | Dispersion = 1.0 | ||||||||
C = 0.5 | C = 0.0 | C = 0.5 | C = 0.0 |
Voting system | Random society | D= 2 | D= 4 | D= 2 | D= 4 | D= 2 | D= 4 | D= 2 | D= 4 |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Plurality | 60 | 21 | 28 | 27 | 42 | 57 | 67 | 61 | 81 |
Runoff | 82 | 31 | 44 | 39 | 62 | 80 | 87 | 79 | 96 |
Hare (IRV) | 88 | 34 | 50 | 38 | 72 | 78 | 86 | 83 | 97 |
Approval | 67 | 73 | 76 | 75 | 82 | 74 | 78 | 81 | 84 |
Borda | 85 | 84 | 87 | 86 | 94 | 86 | 89 | 89 | 92 |
Coombs | 90 | 90 | 91 | 90 | 94 | 97 | 97 | 95 | 97 |
Utility max. | 78 | 80 | 85 | 83 | 86 | 83 | 88 | 88 | 90 |
Elections with a CW | 76% | 98% | 98% | 98% | 99% | 99% | 99% | 99% | 99% |
“Random society” or “impartial culture” is a model of an electorate in which all preference orders (for a set of candidates) are equally likely. “Spatial model” refers to simulations with a normal bell-curve distribution of voters on each issue. A "dispersion" of 1.0 (or medium) means the average distance between candidates’ opinions is as wide as the average distance between voters’ opinions; 0.5 means the candidates tend to be more moderate than the voters. The latter corresponds to the assumption that most candidates seek the large group of voters in the middle of the bell curve. Low dispersion = 0.4 and high = 1.5. C = 0.5 means there is some correspondence between a voter’s position on one issue and his position on others; C = 0.0 means there is no relationship between issues.
The last line shows what percentage of Election which have a Condorcet Winner. Plurality has the worst scores. Runoff and IRV also do poorly in some situations. Often IRV’s flaw results from the squeeze effect. The Condorcet-completion rules by Black, Copeland, Dodgson, Kemeny, Schulze, Tideman and others have Condorcet efficiencies of 100% as does LOR which elects the Condorcet winner when there is one, else the IRV winner. Manipulation of any rule can hide Condorcet winners. A rule’s resistance to manipulation is a key to its Condorcet efficiency in policy votes. Merrill explores Condorcet efficiencies in more complex situations (Merrill, page 39). IRV’s chance of electing the Condorcet candidate drops in a polarized society. Its efficiency rises with rising voter uncertainty about candidates’ positions on issues but it remains lower than most other rule’s. The efficiency of IRV and other non-Condorcet rules drops as the number of candidates increases. Obviously, the elections in which IRV picks the Condorcet winner are a subset of those in which LOR does. voter uncertainty, pre-election polls and “strategic voting” in which each person uses polling information, optimizing his ballot to elect candidates he likes and block those he dislikes. A sim maker's choice of models effects the results. Disregard research that does not use realistic data. Remember: “Garbage in, garbage out.“ To learn about life, use the most normal, lifelike sim. Surveys and actual elections reveal some randomness, some clusters of like-minded voters and some agreement on the candidates’ relative positions left to right. A mixture of random and a normally-distributed voters approximates the observed patterns. But just as random and spatial models lead to different results, so the actual data differs from both of them. Tideman reportedly found that even plurality rule picked the Condorcet winner in 95% of three-candidate elections. He used survey data to simulate rank-order ballots. (Merrill, page 70) This does not recommend plurality since its efficiency drops as the number of contestants rises and all other systems scored higher. Chamberlin and Featherston found similar results when they simulated ballots to resemble the distribution and clustering they found in the APA electorate. So the pattern of opinion dispersion affects Condorcet efficiencies. But the relative standing of the voting systems does not change. Condorcet efficiency has great importance because the winners tend to be the median candidates and a happy result for the greatest number of voters. This is not necessarily the greatest total happiness as utility voting systems attempt to define it. Utility efficiencyThe major competitor to Condorcet efficiency is utility efficiency. It attempts to measure how likely a voting system is to elect the candidate with supporters who feel strongly and opponents who don't much care. Many people are skeptical about trying to compare utility values from one voter to another and to hundreds of voters; so Condorcet efficiency is the most widely accepted measure.[footnote 1: Researchers attempt to make utility measure the "distance" between a candidate and a voter on an issue. They average the scores for all issues to determine the expected utility value of the candidate for that voter. The candidate’s averaged utility score for all voters is said to be her social utility to the electorate. The highest candidate scores from each election in a series of elections are averaged to find the highest average possible. Then the social utility scores of winners under a voting rule are averaged and compared with the highest possible to give theorists a number for the utility of the rule’s utility winners’ efficiency as a percentage of the highest utility possible. Following R.J. Weber (1977), most Researchers subtract a large number of utility points, equal to the score of a randomly selected candidate, from both the utility maximizer and the voting system’s winners. The size of each score is reduced. But the difference between their scores remains the same. So the difference is now a larger percentage of a score. This exaggerates the differences between voting systems on utility efficiency. You must decide whether such exaggeration helps you see the differences or misleads your understanding of these differences. Get definitions from Merrill, Bordley, and Mueller.] [footnote 2: There are several different conceptions of "distance": linear, square root, and logarithmic (Merrill page 42, Bordley), and no standard unit to measure interpersonal utility for all types of issues. For these reasons, many people are skeptical about the meaning, comparison, and statistical manipulation of interpersonal utilities.] |
Table 3. Utility Efficiencies
in computer simulated elections with 5 candidates and 1000 voters.
from Merrill, page 35
Voting Rule | Random Society | D= 2 | D= 4 | D= 2 | Spatial models | D= 2 | D= 4 | D= 2 | D= 4 |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Dispersion = 0.5 | Dispersion = 1.0 | ||||||||
C = 0.5 | C = 0.0 | C = 0.5 | C = 0.0 |
Voting system | Random society | D= 2 | D= 4 | D= 2 | D= 4 | D= 2 | D= 4 | D= 2 | D= 4 |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Plurality | 70 | -1 | 0 | 22 | 52 | 64 | 75 | 74 | 93 |
Runoff | 81 | 28 | 47 | 48 | 75 | 86 | 92 | 88 | 98 |
Hare (IRV) | 82 | 40 | 59 | 52 | 82 | 88 | 92 | 91 | 98 |
Approval | 90 | 96 | 96 | 95 | 98 | 96 | 96 | 97 | 98 |
Borda | 95 | 97 | 97 | 96 | 99 | 98 | 98 | 97 | 99 |
Coombs | 87 | 92 | 92 | 92 | 94 | 96 | 96 | 96 | 98 |
Merrill concludes his chapter on utility efficiency saying that :
“The candidate with the maximum social utility is no more likely to be the Condorcet candidate than is the candidate selected by many if not most of the systems studied. That is to say, the Condorcet criterion and the criterion of maximizing social utility are in fact very different. Whenever the two criteria indicate different winners, the Condorcet winner would beat the utility winner in a one on one election. The problem with all utility voting systems is that a minority of voters can claim on their ballots that their candidate has a much higher utility value for them than any other candidate. With this claim they may be able to “steal” the election from a complacent majority. Distribution of WinnersChamberlin and Cohen’s 1978 spatial-model simulations showed Condorcet picked the candidate “nearest” the “center of the electorate” 87% of the time. I think this suggests a political measure of political outcomes -- in contrast to the economic measure of utility. To measure the dispersions of voters and candidates and the distributions of winners and budget allocations assumes that each citizen has an equal right not only to vote but to be represented and to live under government programs compatible with the citizen’s philosophy. A system that produced proportional outcomes would reduce majority domination of minorities and so make empire building unattractive. The majority would lose some of its autonomy for every increase in territory.Table 4. Nearness to the Center of the Theoretical Electorate
Condorcet has the narrowest distribution around the center. IRV has the second widest. LOR’s distribution of winners will depend on the percentage of elections with natural or manipulated voting cycles. We know that natural cycles are rare in elections but they maybe common when enacting policies. Perhaps Condorcet tends to elect high utility candidates because it directly compares every candidate with each of the others. Simulations by Bordley and Merrill both found Condorcet’s rule picked winners a bit lower in utility than Borda which uses all information in one step. Condorcet certainly beats IRV which uses only first-choice information at each of several steps. Notice that plurality tends to elect the least-favorite candidate, the one toward one edge on a scattergram. That’s because she has no competition for the voters in that area of the electorate. Meanwhile other candidates split-up the first-choice votes from the electorate’s center. You can run simulation experiments with PoliticalSim TM or just play with it enough to get a feel for the tendancies of a few major rules. |
Accurate Democracy | |||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|
Electoral Systems | Legislative Systems | ||||
Reps | Council Condorcet chair plus PR reps | Policy
Condorcet and rules of order | Projects | Budgets |
|